[Introductory notice: this is one of the papers I wrote during my sociology master, which I suspect shines through in patches (e.g. the the first paragraph, and the frequent use of Calhoun et al 2012). Nevertheless, I reckon these words might be more useful in a published state, rather than merely collecting entropy on a hard drive somewhere. Enjoy.]
The learning
objectives state that the student shall display an “in-depth knowledge of
classic sociological theories, concepts, and topics”. This might seem a
straightforward enough proposition at a glance – there is a verb and a noun,
and the relationship between the two is possible to parse grammatically. Upon
closer inspection, particularly through the lens of the theories put forth by
the thinkers categorized under the rubric of ‘classic social theorists’,
matters become ever so slightly more complex. As we shall see, “knowledge” is
situated in the social context at a more general level, rather than in any particular
individual. This makes the notion of an individual “displaying” knowledge
somewhat disingenuous, since it masks the necessarily social dimension of being
in the know. An individual is not possible outside of the social, just as the
social is not possible without individuals. They are mutually constitutive,
meaning that – as Sinatra did sing – you can’t have one without the other.
Kant (2012|1949), for
instance, wrote of the difference between private and public reason. “Private”
here refers to a situation wherein a particular person acts in a particular
circumstance, such as when employed to perform some clerical or administrative
function. In such a situation, there is no room for argument or reasoned
disobedience – the taxes have to be collected, the legitimately given orders
obeyed, the functions of state performed as written. Private reason is
particular, situated. Public reason, on the other hand, addresses a more
generalized audience (“the entire reading public” [p 51]), using all available
arguments and evidence to make the best, most reasoned case possible. Public
reason is not concerned with the specifics of how the arguments laid forth
inconvenience or embarrass the powers that be – it merely seeks the truth for
its own sake, based on the available and through logic sustainable lines of
argument put forth in previous applications of public reason. Later on, Matthew
Arnold (1864) would phrase public reason in terms of using “the best possible
knowledge” (with the added probabilistic observation that the likelihood that
we already possess this knowledge is low, and that we thus should be on
perpetual lookout for it).
From this one
distinction alone, the issue of displaying knowledge becomes a question of just
what kind of reason is sought after. Are students asked to display an apt
performance of private reason, thus showing that they are fit for this or that
employment or some other particular niche contingency relevant to the
university at hand? Or are the students asked to perform a more generally
applicable form of reason, regardless of whether it is relevant to the private
situation of anyone involved?
To be sure, learning
objective number six states that students shall act in a critical and
independent manner, which at a glance would suggest a preference for public
reason. It is, however, possible to be critical and independent in the
application of private reason as well – many a philosopher (Hegel, Heidegger,
take your pick) have found themselves justifying what the state apparatus would
have done anyway, albeit with less scripture to fall back on. Add to this the
ever mounting pressure to self-regulate in all domains of life, rather than to
merely conform to previously given decrees, and we are back to asking whether
private or public reason is the order of the day.
From here, it might be
fruitful to jump over to Benjamin (2012|1969) and the tendency of modern
fascism to incorporate public reason into its private functioning. Or, in his
terms, the tendency of fascism to reproduce any work of art in such quantities
as to render its qualities irrelevant. No matter how egalitarian or progressive
a work might have been upon creation, once it has been incorporated within the
fascist aesthetic the work is subsumed to whatever teleology professed by the
state. Not necessarily due to flawed efforts on the part of the artist, but due
to how the mass production of art distorts and affects artworks: the endless
repetition of a unified aesthetic reduces any particular element of it to
merely a component, a replaceable part of an ideological machine. Whatever the
conditions of an artwork’s production, its reproduction into a new context
renders it moot. Context trumps content.
The challenge
presented by Benjamin is to create works which nevertheless resist this
reduction. While he does not go as far as Adorno & Horkheimer (2012|2002),
who claim that the entirety of what is produced by the culture industry (which
is to say, anything an ordinary person can reasonably expect to encounter by
means of purchase) is a rigged game, Benjamin does acknowledge the difficulty
of being genuine whilst also being widely distributed. A painting – existing in
singular – invites viewers to partake of its particular aura and peculiar
circumstance. A poster – existing in multitudes – invites a very different mode
of engagement. The former has the potential to move viewers, while the latter
is more prone to mobilize them. The aim is to foster appreciation of the few
paintings that remain their own contexts, whilst not falling for the lure of
producing too many posters whilst trying to make a living.
This is, I reckon, a
more contemporary version of Kant’s distinction between private and public
reason. There is no small irony in the fact that the mass-produced, ubiquitous
forms of art that are available to everyone, and thus present in everyone’s
private homes, while the manifestations of public reasoning have become rare and
hard to come by. More so as universities are under pressure to become relevant
to the job market – to subsume their commitment to public reasoning to private
interests, in all senses of the word.
In all this, it
becomes difficult for a student to know how to proceed in order to fulfil the
learning objectives. On the one hand, an overt commitment to public reason is
unlikely to be rejected on explicit or ideological grounds – these are, after
all, the values enshrined into academia by virtue of hundreds of years of
tradition and continual practice. On the other hand, there is – as Merton
(2012|1949) pointed out – a need to distinguish between manifest and latent
functions of social practices. The stated goals of an organization might not be
the entire story of what this organization is actually doing, sociologically
speaking, and merely identifying the manifest function in ideological terms
does not provide the full picture of what needs to be learnt in order for the
objectives to be deemed fulfilled. Merely knowing the official story means
knowing nothing at all, which – Socrates notwithstanding – is not a comfortable
situation to find oneself in[1].
Again we are
confronted with the vagaries involved with the individual display of knowledge.
There are, as it were, two kinds of knowledge in circulation, both of which
have to be present in equal measure for the display to be valid. There is the
obvious, explicit knowledge of what different authors wrote and how their ideas
interact with each other. And then there is the implicit familiarity with the
tradition of the discipline, the injokes, the informal sentiments, the
recurring themes, and other ephemeral yet foundational aspects of a body of
knowledge. Displaying one form of knowledge without the other would not pass
muster; the display would be found lacking in either substance or soul.
Here, it is
illuminating to view the educational process as a gradual initiation into a
community, rather than as a series of tests to be undergone and passed. To be
sure, undergoing the tests is still an integral part of the project, but their
latent function is to ever so gradually become more socialized into the
discipline and its customs. Being a sociologist – or indeed belonging to any
academic discipline – is more akin to possessing an attitude or a worldview
than anything else, and can not be reduced to knowing the contents of a
discrete set of foundational texts. As rigorous and systematic as the
evaluation criteria might wish to appear, a core part of determining whether an
education has succeeded comes down to whether a student gets it or not. Or, to return to Benjamin: the quality sought is
made plain in the difference between appreciating a painting and plastering a
poster.
These are not
qualities that exist as independent measurable variables which can be isolated
and controlled for using ever so systematic metrics and procedures. Rather,
they are constitutive of and inherent to the very situation the education takes
place in. What is evaluated is not whether the student knows this or that, but
whether they manage to comport themselves in such a manner that the
conversation keeps flowing without interruption.[2]
To invoke Bakhtin (1986), it is more important to be aware of genre (defined as
a series of social expectations on frequently recurring situations) than to
know exactly which year a particular author published their seminal work. A
student gets more mileage out of gesturing towards a shared exhaustion from
reading a particularly painstaking introduction, than they derive from
paraphrasing it with unerring accuracy.
A pragmatic student
would apply Mead (2012|1934) to this dynamic. Mead differentiates between the
“I” and the “me”. The “I” is the stream of impressions, thoughts and emotions
that occur in any given moment. The “me”, in contrast, is a gestalt self-image
which takes into account all aspects of one’s place in a local and global
social context. The “I” uses whatever information is retained in/of the “me” to
orient itself and plan its upcoming course of actions. Our imaginary pragmatic
student would shift the goal of the educational process from the I to the me –
rather than seeing it as an individualistic trait that can be summoned or
performed at any given moment, it is rather a characteristic of the social
situation they happen to find themselves in upon nearing the completion of
their education. Rather than hitting the books, they would seek out social
gatherings in which to gain insight into the social processes at work within
their field, and possibly wherein they could get recognition as belonging to
the very same community. To pun: the important thing is not whether I know this
or that, bur whether they know me.
The learning objectives,
however, remain on the level of individual assessment. The student, singular,
shall display their acumen through individual effort. The goals are framed in
such a way that the knowledge is situated within the student, as so many crates
in a warehouse, rather than as a more general proficiency to draw upon the
collective fount of shared resources, references and reflections. There is an
inherent contradiction between the praxis of performing academics and the
stated learning objectives. The former heavily emphasizes surveying the
collective state of the field, of surveying the literature and probing the
limits of established disciplinary achievement. The latter collapses all of
that into a single unit of performance, and applies a single value to it. The
student either knows or does not know – a binary solution to a complex social
dynamic.
This contradiction
might seem a subtle point, but it manifests very directly in everyday
educational situations. The most overt example is when a student asks whether
some concept or theorist is going to be on the exam. From the point of view of
being introduced to the discipline’s traditions and tools, this is the least
interesting (and most parochial) question that could possibly exist – an entire
history of knowledge is reduced to a single social situation in the near
future. From the point of view of the student, who sees that the only thing
they need to do is to perform the learning objectives, this is a rational
inquiry which could provide useful information upon which to structure their
efforts. If a theorist appears on the exam, then being able to reiterate the
general outline of their thoughts is a demonstrably good thing; if said
theorist is not on the exam, then focusing on the theorists that do appear is a
more rational option. It is a far cry from engaging in public reason, but it
achieves the learning objectives. Why appreciate a painting when plastering a
poster does the job just fine?
Here, the reader might
object that a student asking whether something appears on an exam or not is an
indication that they lack the proper insight into what the point of higher
learning is. Which is fair as far as it goes, but it does highlight that this
very point ultimately boils down to whether or not the student gets it, in the manner discussed above.
Too direct and explicit focus on the process of passing the educational
obstacles and jumping through all the hoops draws attention away from the very
goal to be achieved. Learning objectives and learning outcomes diverge, despite
their grammatical similarity.
This is, of course,
not a new observation. Quintilian (1987|95) noted that every educational situation
is a unique context with its own dynamics, wherein the values and virtues to be
inculcated have to be reaffirmed anew, lest the pupils learn something else.
The reasons for learning something are as important as learning the thing in
itself. Quintilian uses memorization of literary passages as an example of this
dynamic. The desired outcome is not that the pupils can regurgitate the
selected passage on command, but to show them that being able to access a wide
range of literary sources will help guide them in their efforts at living a
good life, where everyday occurrences are connected to greater themes and thus
possible to analyze as parts of a whole, rather than as individual incidents.
The whole is greater than the sum of its parts, and the goal of a Quintilian
education is to ever so gently point towards the greater picture.
Dewey (2005), in
slightly more contemporary terms, made the same observation when he noted that
pupils only ever learn what they are interested in, and that education is only
as effective as it is capable of capturing this interest. An explanatory
lecture on the finer points of algebra might be effective in conveying
information pertaining to math, but it might also be a fine opportunity to
practice falling asleep whilst sitting in a room with various degrees of
directed noise. The latter is motivated by a very clear and directly applicable
use value, while the former requires a higher degree of contextual introduction
to come to pass. Both outcomes are equally likely, and both learners are
equally motivated.
A way to rectify the
situation would be to punish those who are not interested. Or, rather, those
who fail to learn. This would introduce a very clear motivation to be
interested in the topic at hand, and very concrete reasons to perform the tasks
laid out. It would also, with equal clarity, reframe the situation as being
about avoiding punishment, rather than as ultimately striving to reach some
sort of more refined worldview with access to the tools of reason and
rationality. At best, it would be an inefficient didactic methodology. At
worst, it would be an attempt to force individuals to freely participate in
public reasoning, a proposition quite contrary to what Kant envisioned.
The overarching
project in de Beauvoir’s Second Sex (2011)
is to underscore all the ways in which women – historically and at present – have
been formally and informally barred from participating in public reason. By
describing in detail every aspect of women’s lives – youth, menstruation,
marriage, sex, rape, pregnancy, housework, prostitution – she also describes
what makes women other when compared
to men, the implicit default. These aspects are peculiar, particular and personal. More specifically, they create a different
starting point from which to engage the world, a different social and epistemic
staging ground from which to launch any attempt at participation, be it in politics
or public reason. There are men, the universal subject who tackles universal
issues with the tools of rationality and reason, and there are women, who
tackles the particular, emotional and utterly local. Men are constructed as
universal, women are constructed as other.
The efforts of
McDonald (2004) are indicative of this state of affairs. Her ambition to gather
and introduce female social theorists is not motivated by trying to justify
women’s peculiar or different contributions over the centuries. Rather, it is
an attempt to draw attention to how these contributions follow the same
developmental lines as male theorists, using the same tools and more often than
not the same lines of arguments. There are not two differing historical tracks,
male and female, which never interacted with each other as time passed. Rather,
theorists from both genders engaged in lively and fruitful debate where the
results were a better understanding of the contemporary social and political
situation. To quote: “[t]he problem, after all, is not that the women founders
of the social sciences failed to publish but that the scholarly world failed to
recognize their work” (p 242).
McDonald (2004) notes
that the omission of female theorists from the canon of social thinkers has had
the unfortunate consequence that many contemporary social theorists have felt
as if they started from scratch, and based their approaches to the social sciences
on this premise. Rather than being able to draw upon the rich tradition of
female authors discussing women’s issues – in the broadest possible use of the
term – these efforts have been hampered by a lack of theoretical underpinning
and a sense of methodological commitment to qualitative approaches. Given that
all social theorists presented in the canonical works are men, women had to
carve out a niche for themselves, theoretically as well as institutionally.
Needless to say, this
redoubling of otherness, as described by de Beauvoir, has not done the study of
women’s issues (or women’s studies) any favors. It has framed the feminist
approach as somehow optional, something to do above and beyond the real work,
an excursion into private reason only allowed once the appropriate work has
been performed with regards to public reason. To put it in the bluntest
possible terms, it creates a dichotomy which is nigh impossible to overcome:
there are public intellectuals, and there are women.
Neither has it done
any favors to individual women, who – to gain access to positions in academia,
and thus the right to participate in the conversation – have had to read
through an extensive amount of theory which only marginally concern a large
portion of their lived experience. Which is not to say that this theory is
irrelevant or inapplicable, but it introduces something of a delay to getting started
with the actual work. There is a lot of universal theory to power through
before being allowed to proceed with the particulars, where every step of the
way has to be retraced to theories which do not take the lived experience of
women into account[3].
The barrier to entry into public reason consists of a non-trivial amount of
hoops, some more onerous than others.
Given this state of
affairs, we could use Simmel’s (2012|1971) theory of group dynamics to predict
that feminist scholars in different fields will have an easier time of
collaborating with each other than would non-feminists. According to Simmel,
one group functions more or less like any other group, despite their overt
differences. Thus, performing the work necessary to maintain some particular
function in one group creates a kinship with those who perform the same work in
other groups, by virtue of a shared range of experiences and skills. Applied to
feminist scholars, who (regardless of field) have had to struggle for the
inclusion of actually existing women into the historical canon, there is bound
to be a rich potential for interdisciplinary cooperation to draw upon in future
efforts.
To return to the
question of learning objectives, this places objectives 1 and 2 in a precarious
position. On the one hand, women have been excluded from the canonical writs of
the history of sociology to such an extent that the official history has become
almost exclusively male; any effort to accurately describe the historiography
of the field must take this social fact into account. On the other hand,
efforts to include female authors are under way at present, and part of these
efforts is the inclusion of these very same authors in new rewritings of the
same history. The question then becomes whether to report on the history of
sociology as written, or to give an
account which includes actually existing social thinkers who have not yet been
labelled as sociological. Both courses of action follow from the learning
objectives as they stand.
Of course, contextual
evidence suggest that the second approach is to be preferred (such as the
inclusion of McDonald 2004 in the syllabus), but this bounces us straight back
to informal knowledge guiding the process of adhering to formally stated goals.
What is asked for is not knowledge of the history of sociology in general, but
a very specific subset of a very specific categorization of history of
sociology with a local emphasis. History is indeed, as Cannadine (2011) noted,
a situated activity in the present.
An attentive reader
will have noted the parallels between the global and the local, the state of
the field and the state of the syllabus. Sociological theory is not a static
thing that can either be known or not known; rather, it is a dynamic and ever
changing ethos formed as much by tradition as by propositional statements made
by individual theorists. Thus, evaluating whether a student knows sociological
theory or not becomes a somewhat extracurricular activity. To be sure, knowing one’s
Weber and Durkheim is important, but it is equally important to know them for
the right reasons[4].
As Quintilian pointed out, merely going through the motions is insufficient; a
successful education will have had the student approach the subject matter in an
appropriate manner, the manner being of greater import than the matter. The
same applies to the teaching of sociological theory, mutatis mutandis.
This frame of
reference is rather far removed from the contemporary tendency of envisioning
education as a series of boxes to tick off, where the educational aims have
been achieved in full once each and every aspect has been individually
fulfilled. I reckon that Merton’s distinction between manifest and latent
functions is very much at play in this tendency. We can not take the learning
objectives at their words – that would be akin to analyzing rain dances only
with regards to their efficacy at making it rain. There are far more
interesting social processes at work, and it is very fortunate that we as sociologists
are uniquely positioned to analyze these processes using the traditional tools
of our trade. They only need to be applied appropriately.
[1] The same goes for reading syllabi. As Wahlström (2015) points out, these
documents are situated in a political, institutional, ideological and sometimes
didactical context, where the specific content is determined by a number of
competing forces vying for influence. And, I might add, merely reading the
syllabi, words on a page, does not translate into knowing what transpires in
classrooms or seminars.
[2] Bourdieu (1990) describes this process, and points out that students
from middle and upper class backgrounds have an advantage over their fellow
students from working class backgrounds. Where the former carry a habitus
suitable for performing academics (albeit still with a need to be socialized
into a particular discipline), the latter have to pull double duty of both
reading the required literature and relearning their way of being in the social
world. They have to learn to be middle class as well as mastering the subject
matter, as it were.
[3] Being behind Rawl’s veil of ignorance takes on a substantially different
quality should you happen to be pregnant.
[4] Weber wrote extensively on 19th century economics, and
Durkheim famously made reference to phrenology as a legitimate scientific
method. Building an argument on these two historically accurate propositions is
not likely to garner favor in the contemporary sociological community, however;
it would be an inappropriate approach.
References
Adorno, T. &
Horkheimer, M. (2002). The dialectic of enlightenment: philosophical fragments.
In
Calhoun et al (ed) (2012): Classical sociological theory. Chichester:
Wiley-Blackwell.
Arnold, M. (1864). The
function of criticism at the present time. The National Review, November 1864.
Bakhtin, M. (1986).
Speech genres & other late essays. Austin: University of Texas Press.
Beauvoir, de, S.
(2011). The second sex. Ney York: Vintage Books.
Bourdieu, P. &
Passeran, J-C. (1990). Reproduction in education, society and culture. London:
Sage.
Benjamin, W. (1969).
The work of art in the age of mechanical reproduction. In Calhoun et al (ed)
(2012): Classical sociological theory. Chichester: Wiley-Blackwell.
Cannadine, D. (2011).
Making history now and then: discoveries, controversies and explorations.
Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.
Dewey, J. (2005). Democracy
and education: an introduction to the philosophy of education. New York: Cosimo
Classics.
Kant, I. (1949). What
is enlightenment? In Calhoun et al (ed) (2012): Classical sociological theory. Chichester:
Wiley-Blackwell.
McDonald, L. (2004).
Women founders of the social sciences. Montréal, Québec: McGill-Queen's
University Press.
Merton, R. (1949).
Social theory and social structure. In Calhoun et al (ed) (2012): Classical
sociological theory. Chichester: Wiley-Blackwell.
Quintilian. (1987). Quintilian
on the teaching of speaking and writing: translations from books one, two, and
ten of the Institutio oratoria. Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press.
Simmel, G. (1971).
Georg Simmel: on individuality and social forms. In Calhoun et al (ed) (2012):
Classical sociological theory. Chichester: Wiley-Blackwell.
Wahlström, N. (2015).
Läroplansteori och didaktik. Malmö: Gleerups.